Interdisciplinary institute for innovation
Interdisciplinary Institute for Innovation
Behind the scenes of scientific
articles: defining categories of
fraud and regulating cases
David Pontille
Working Paper 13-MS-03
Centre de sociologie de l'innovation
MINES ParisTech, CNRS UMR 7185
60 boulevard Saint Michel
75272 Paris Cedex 06, France
Behind the scenes of scientific articles:
defining categories of fraud and regulating cases
David Pontille
Center for the Sociology of Innovation (CSI)
CNRS (UMR 7185) – Mines ParisTech
[email protected]
Didier Torny*
Risques, Travail, Marchés, État (RiTME)
INRA (UR 1323)
[email protected]
Introduction
On March 7, 2012, the blog
Retraction Watch1 announced that Yoshitaka Fujii, Associate
Professor of Anesthesiology, had just been fired from the University of Toho for having
published nine clinical studies that did not comply with the current ethical guidelines. The
blog also announced that one of the journals concerned,
Anesthesia & Analgesia, whose
subtitle is "the gold standard in anesthesiology," revealed in a communiqué that a study of
the integrity of Dr. Fujii's research had been launched in 2010 (Schafer 2012). The journal's
American editor-in-chief indicated that 24 other articles could be the subject of scientific
fraud. He also stated that in 2000 his journal had published a letter from German researchers
presenting a meta-analysis of 47 articles jointly signed by Dr. Fujii (Kranke et al. 2012).
These authors underscore the remarkably identical frequency of headaches as side effects
of anesthesia in all studies and concluded that only an underlying influence could explain this
stupefying consistency.
Dr. Fujii had responded with a short jointly published letter, simply indicating that he had reported empirical observations and that they were expected given the state of knowledge. This response was sufficiently convincing to the
International Anesthesia Research Society that Dr. Fujii was able to publish 12 additional articles over the following decade. Yet the German researchers had pursued their meta-analyses, in 2001 showing in
Acta Anaesthesiologica Scandinavica that 64% of the clinical data published for an antiemetic originated from Dr. Fujii's team, even though his dosage results diverged substantially from those produced by all of the other laboratories (Kranke et al. 2001). Following this
* Both authors contributed equally to data collection and processing, to the analysis, and to writing the article. This working paper has been published in French in
Revue d'Epidémiologie et de Santé Publique, 2012, vol. 60(4), p. 247-253. 1 http://retractionwatch.wordpress.com/
publication, the authors alerted the Food and Drug Administration and the Japanese regulatory agency, apparently to no avail.
In March 2010, an editorial in the British journal
Anaesthesia described the obstacles to demonstrating falsification and the invention of clinical data, taking as an example the suspicions weighing against Dr. Fujii's data (Moore et al. 2010). This editorial provoked a large number of responses, leading editorial boards to engage in a reflection on their role in combatting scientific fraud (Wagner 2012). Also, in 2011 when Dr. Fujii submitted an article to the
Canadian Journal of Anesthesia, where he had already published 39 articles, the journal opened an inquiry with the University of Toho, which revealed that there was no Committee for the protection of human research subjects, prompting investigations on all of his research production (Miller 2012). At the same time, a meta-analysis of 169 controlled trials cosigned by Dr. Fujii, initiated following the 2010 editorial and verified at length, was published as a special article in
Anaesthesia on March 8, 2012. It concluded that the distribution of 28 of the variables published did not correspond to what could be expected, with the probability of occurrence under the hypothesis of independence even reaching 10−33 for one of them (Carlisle 2012).
Finally, on April 9, 2012, a joint letter from 22 editorial directors was addressed to the leaders of nine institutions that had hosted Dr. Fujii's research and simultaneously published on some of the journals' web sites. It informed them of the publication of this study and announced that the articles would be retracted, unless the institutions involved could provide proof that the articles were trustworthy: "for each study concerned, we request that your institution declare 1/ that the study was conducted as presented in the article, 2/ that you have examined the primary data and verified that they were authentic, and 3/ that the appropriate ethical framework was clearly established for the study" (Collectif 2012). Answering that call, the Japanese Society of Anesthesiologists led an inquiry and concluded, in its 29th June 2012 report, that 172 articles jointly signed by Dr Fujii contained falsified data and should be retracted, which is an unequaled record for a single author.
How can one explain that Dr. Fujii was able to publish apparently falsified data for such a long time? Is this an isolated researcher who was particularly skilled in fabricating forgeries corresponding to the expectations of the scientific community, including those of his coauthors2? Is this a local institutional problem related to his mandarin status, as in the case of Professor W.S. Hwang, a Korean national hero and fraudulent inventor of human cloning (Gottweis & Kim 2009)? Are we dealing with a disciplinary idiosyncrasy, since two other anesthesiologists have recently undergone similar waves of retracted articles and that 4% of the articles submitted to
Anaesthesia have turned out to be plagiarized (Yentis 2010)? Or should we consider that any academic production is potentially tarnished, implicating all scientific institutions (authors, financers, editors, journals) (Ioannidis 2005)?
Two major interpretations are generally contrasted in this type of situation. The first tolls the bell of scientific integrity: it is mainly based on the massive increase of the number of articles retracted (Van Noorden 2011), on the fact that these retractions are strongly correlated with the journals' impact factor (Fang & Casadevall 2011) or that the retractions for fraud take
2 Let us not forget the brilliant physicist J.H. Schön, covered with prizes and the lead author of eight articles published in
Science and seven articles published in
Nature between 2000 and 2001, but then fired by Bell Labs
and whose dissertation was revoked by the University of Constance.
place in journals with a higher impact factor than the retractions for experimental or calculation errors (Steen 2011a). It also responds to the high frequency of researchers declaring having observed colleagues involved in practices they deem contrary to scientific ethics (Fanelli 2009). In contrast, the second interpretation ferociously defends tooth and nail a model of self-regulation. It is founded, for example, on the usually brief time between publication and retraction, the generally low number of citations related to these articles (Furman et al. 2012), the appearance in some journals of temporary publication bans, and considers the creation of specialized places such as the
Abnormal Science and
Retraction Watch blogs as extensions of peer review (Marcus & Oransky 2011).
Our objective in this article is not to choose between these two positions, which stabilized over the 1980s (Broad & Wade 1982; Lafolette 1992) and were regularly reactivated by other actors with each new case detected. Instead, from a perspective informed by science and technology studies, we wish to establish a general diagnosis on the regulation of publication practices and suggest methods of analysis, by reviewing both the recent cases and others, less recent, that they call to mind. First of all, this paper reviews how the practices deemed to be deviant have been qualifed in the past by distinguishing the categories stemming from data integrity and the conditions of data production from those concerning the relationships between the authors of publications and their content. We will then analyze three specific problems and the institutional responses aiming to prevent them, channel them, and attempt to solve them.
Striking it rich with dubious data
Medical research for the most part has been marked by a progressive rise in ethical
demands that strive toward defining the quality of the data produced. The need to collect
informed consent from the subjects participating in therapeutic research is a good example,
the subject of a vast literature on its concrete manifestations (Corrigan 2003). Similarly, in the
construction of all the instruments designed for direct or indirect use in epidemiological
studies, protecting the subjects' anonymity is essential to conducting these investigations.
These diverse ethical demands frame the conditions of data production: any time compliance
is lacking, the reliability of the data is compromised for this reason alone, as seen with the
case of Dr. Fujii. But the materials on which the results published are founded can be subject
to tampering beyond these regulatory obligations.
Several ways of contravening "good practices" can be identified in the series of affairs discussed herein. The first resides in the selection of relevant data to obtain more coherent results, a smoother curve, a more readable image. R. Fisher, an important statistician, geneticist, and support for eugenics, 80 years after the famous experiments by Gregor Mendel on his peas, showed, for example, that the probabilities obtained were undoubtedly too good to be true and stemmed more from a confirmation bias than from an observation. His research has contributed to designing tools to remove the biases introduced by experimenters, notably in controlled clinical trials (Marks 1999). In this process of selecting relevant data, the question of ill will is secondary to all the possible means of deviating from an experimental, observational, or statistical norm.
The second consists in conscious falsification activities, which can manifest as minor arrangements of experimental material, falsification of data, or manipulation of images. D.
Das, a surgeon working on the protective effects of resveratrol, explaining
in fine the probable role played by wine consumption in the French Paradox, was suspected of having massively doctored Western blot images that were the basis of dozens of articles that he published, leading to his being fired from the University of Connecticut after 3 years of inquiry (DeFrancesco 2012). The multiplication of cases raising questions on the falsification of images reveals just how fragile and uncertain are the graphic representations that are held to be tangible components of scientific proof in the end (Lynch & Woolgar 1990), and raises debate on the nature of the data necessary to certify their integrity.
Finally, the third manner stems from fabrication pure and simple. Falsification extends here to all materials and is based on the pure invention of data. The example of the physician and dentist Jon Sudbø comes to mind, who, in 2006, admitted to having literally created 900 patients in a Norwegian cohort, 250 of whom had the same date of birth. This allowed him to demonstrate spectacular effects of taking nonsteroidal anti-inflammatory drugs on oral cancer in heavy smokers and to publish in
The Lancet the year before.
The distinction between selection, falsification, and fabrication is not self-evident and instead comes from
ex post attribution when cases are revealed after investigations (Fanelli 2009). As in the affairs concerning Prof. Hwang, when there are no detailed admissions, it is impossible to distinguish between what has been authentically produced in the laboratory and what is instead voluntary or involuntary artifact. If the absence of reproducibility is often considered a clue to falsification, the opposite is not necessarily true: a highly skilled forger can produce a sort of retroplagiarism, arranging or fabricating data that others, through slow scientific work, will have actually produced and analyzed.
Circumventing proof of originality
One of the fundamental principles of scientific activity consists in producing original results,
as indicated by the categorization of journal articles that distinguishes "original research"
from "reviews", "letters", and "editorials." According to this principle, the recognition of one's
peers and the awarding of prizes are strongly related to the priority of original discovery. No
importance is supposedly accorded to second place. Among the different ways to get around
this requirement, this section will emphasize the question of plagiarism and authorship.
Plagiarism and self-plagiarism
In these conditions, the temptation is sometimes great to cite only partially and sporadically
the similar work that has preceded, or even to totally omit its mention. In our era of electronic
publications and cut-and-paste, there is no simpler operation than to insert one or several
paragraphs written and published earlier by others into an article being written, for example
by copying a piece of text from an article on nosocomial infections in Brazil into an article on
the same subject in Spain (Cisterna et al. 2011). The same clearly holds true for data,
figures, and images.
At times fraud is not limited to partial plagiarism: at the end of the 1970s, E. Alsabti, an alleged researcher in oncoimmunology, without a doctorate, succeeded in climbing the ladder of an academic career by putting together an impressive list of publications in barely 3 years (Broad & Wade 1982, chap. 3). His tactic was simple: he copied entire articles that had already been published, modified the title, replaced the authors' names with his own,
and submitted the manuscript to a less well-known journal. He succeeded in accumulating more than 60 publications in this way, in joining 11 scientific societies and in working in several prestigious American institutions.
Rather than borrowing from others' work, it can be even simpler to dig into one's own data. What researchers and clinicians have long designated as a "pressure to publish" (Maddox 1988) has turned into the proliferation of articles based on the same research, the spawning of similar results into a variety of texts and the preference for quantity to the detriment of quality (Hamilton 1990). The practice of self-plagiarism has developed to such an extent that it has progressively given rise to terms such as "least publishable unit" (Broad 1981), "salami slicing" (Huth 1986), and even "duplicate publication" (Susser & Yankauer 1993), and the effects on meta-analyses can be considerable (Tramèr et al. 1997). Even if, contrary to plagiarizing others, this censured concealment is interpreted in a variety of fashions, everyone agrees that the basis of the problem lies in the absence of a citation of the original study (Freund et al. 2012).
Authorship
An alternative manner to bypass the requirements for originality is to maneuver around the
edges of authorship. In many domains, the guidelines regulating access to article byline
place value on significant intellectual contributions. Yet the suspected articles often carry the
name of researchers whose contribution is considered minimal, if not inexistent, and
therefore these individuals have a very distant contact with the research conducted and the
results published. Since the end of the 1980s, researchers and journal editors have
produced, in what is generally called "honorary authorship", three categories of authorship to
denounce these situations that they judge unacceptable (Rennie & Flanagin 1994; Flanagin
et al. 1998).
The first designates "guest authorship", which separately treats people whose name is recognized: these are particular names that change the status accorded to an article by their presence alone. The presence of these researchers' names potentially increases the chances of the article publication and its future visibility and thus figures as a sign of quality. This practice is current and arises in many cases. The affair of the cardiologist J.R. Darsee, one of the most closely followed and documented in the 1980s, brought this practice to the light of day: other than the presence of falsified and entirely invented data, the 55 publications that were retracted often carried the name of his mentor, E. Braunwald, who had little knowledge of their content, and who had not been worried during the detailed investigations of the NIH investigators (Stewart & Feder 1987).
Another category, which plays less on this distinction of status or renown, emphasizes more the offer of authorship governed by the principle of reciprocity, as a gift in view of a counter-gift ("gift authorship"): it is not exceptional that researchers accept to make room for someone so as not to offend a partner making the request, to encourage future collaborations, to maintain good cooperative relations, to thicken a list of publications, or to return the favor (Pontille 2004). In this context, the above-mentioned case of E. Alsabti, nonetheless revealed an extreme and particular form of gift at the time: some of his articles included the names of fictitious authors whom E. Alsabti, at the beginning of his fall, blamed entirely for the abuses for which he was denounced.
Finally, as with other types of writing, notably literary, the name of the writer is not systematically the name of those who appear on the byline ("ghost authorship"). This is notably the case when a researcher, who does the greatest share of the work and writes all or nearly all an article, allows only his students or less experienced colleagues to be the authors of the article so as to assist them in publishing in a prestigious journal and thus lengthen their publications list.
Institutional regulations
Common reactions in the event of practices deemed deviant consist in reaffirming the
general principles at the foundation of scientific integrity: disinterestedness, organized
skepticism regularly held as cardinal virtues (Merton 1942; Weed & McKeown 1998) and
stipulated in charters and professional agreements or through specialized structures within
professional or learned societies (Coughlin 1997). These reactions also require more
restrictive concrete operations aiming to prevent and limit these phenomena by indirect
actions. We will examine here three specific operations relative to responsibility, negative
results, and conflicts of interest.
Restore responsibility
In an evaluation system that values individual performance, the increase of the number of
authors per article is regularly described. Although guest and gift authorship cast doubt on
the attribution of scientific credit, other forms are even more surprising. Some cases, most
particularly the above-mentioned J.R. Darsee affair, revealed that some authors were not
aware that their name had been adjoined to the suspected publications. The journals
consequently took control to defend their self-regulatory function. They sought to return
responsibility to the authors in two major steps. The first resulted from the many cases of
fraud that shook the 1980s: statements are required, signed by all of an article's producers to
ensure that they approve the content and that they indeed intended their name to appear on
the article.
The second step played out between 1996 and 2000, following heated debates between researchers, journal editors, and research administrators (Biagioli 1998; Pontille 2001). They aimed to set up traceability of research operations so as to be able to reattribute responsibility in case of a future problem (Torny 2003). After several conferences and an experimental phase, journals opted for a new procedure, called "contributorship", which promotes transparency: systematically describe the individual contributions in a section of the article specifically designed for this purpose. Before publication, each contributor is now invited to either describe his or her contribution in a written note, or to fill out a form that delineates a taxonomy of research operations. Thus the producers of articles should approve the final version of the text and date their engagement: each one dates and signs the letter or form manually. This procedure reinforces the judicial responsibility of the handwritten signature and forces each contributor to take responsibility for his or her contribution.
Publishing negative results
Whether the result of self-censure or fraudulent practices on the part of researchers, or the
practice of journals for visibility or financial reasons (Smith 2005), publication biases favoring
positive studies are well known (Simes 1986; Stern & Simes 1997). The additional effect of
this bias is relegating negative results to second-rank journals (Kanaan et al. 2011) or even non-publication. This has been demonstrated for antidepressants, for example (Turner et al. 2008), and for a number of substances approved by the Food and Drug Administration between 1998 and 2000 (Lee et al. 2008), to such an extent that certain researchers now take the rate of positive results published as a transdisciplinary indicator of fraud or bias (Fanelli 2010) and others speak of "evidence-biased medicine" (Melander et al. 2003).
To solve this problem, two complementary solutions have been proposed. For clinical studies, this means founding academic evaluation of drugs based on applications made to the regulatory agencies rather than on the published literature (Turnet et al. 2012). In addition, certain journals propose systematically publishing negative results for all types of research, such as the
Journal of Errology or the
Journal of Negative Results in Biomedicine, which has an "unofficial" impact factor of 1.1. These journals consider that unexpected and failed results are important in scientific knowledge, thus returning to one of the founding principles of experimental practice of the seventeenth century, initiated notably by Robert Boyle at the Royal Society of Sciences of London (Shapin & Schaffer 1985).
Uncover and reduce conflicts of interest
A third question brings together all of the problematic aspects described in the first sections:
conflict of interest. This notion was imported into the scientific world in the 1960s to describe
the increasing relations between public research and industry, and the problems that this
could raise, in particular in expert consultations with health and environmental regulatory
agencies (Gingras & Gosselin 2008). It is through this prism of conflict of interest, for
example, that the accusations of scientific fraud against Dr. Needleman were interpreted by
two of his colleagues while the Environmental Protection Agency had just adopted restrictive
measures for the lead industry (Rosner 2005). More generally, in environmental
epidemiology, the consequences in terms of regulating results in public health have led the
chemical, tobacco, and asbestos industries to not only finance research that was favorable to
them (Pearce 2008), but also to maintain uncertainty over the long term to fight against
stabilized knowledge being established (Proctor & Schiebinger 2008).
With the ever-increasing meshing and merging of financing from the pharmaceutical industry and academics, the notion of conflict of interest in its contemporary sense truly appeared in the 1980s (Gingras & Gosselin 2008): it was thus repeatedly demonstrated that financing from industry or pharmaceutical laboratories influenced the results produced (Abraham 1994; Bekelman 2003; Friedman & Richter 2004; Lexchin et al. 2003), including on subtile modalities such as the favorable presentation of hormone replacement treatments well after their risk–benefit ratio was challenged at the beginning of the 2000s (Fugh-Berman et al. 2001). In this context, Elsevier was denounced for creating six seemingly scientific journals that were actually financed by pharmaceutical laboratories and designed to present compilations of articles that were favorable to them (Hansen 2012). Certain forms of ghostwriting
also stem from this practice: through specialized companies, the pharmaceutical firms, once the research and articles had been completed, requested researchers who were reputed in their specialty to sign the publications in exchange for consequential financial compensation (Mirowski 2005; Sismondo 2007).
With reform in mind, institutions and journals began including the financing sources and conflict of interest disclosures as a solution to these problems, with, for example, regular
guidelines by the
International Committee of Medical Journal Editors beginning in 19933, even though their implementation took an exceedingly long time in the eyes of their detractors (Krimsky & Rothenberg 2001). Others have suggested radical reforms of complete separation between private interests and public research (Schafer 2004), a position recently found on expert testimony in the parliamentary discussions after the Mediator French scandal. However, everyone agrees that internal transformations of scientific production, most particularly biomedical research, has made a large number of researchers true entrepreneurs (Etzkowitz 1996). The case of A. Potti illustrates these tensions: as soon as his first articles on genomic markers of the sensitivity of different chemotherapies were published in
Nature Medicine and the
New England Journal of Medicine in 2006, Duke University and his team boasted of "personalized medicine" that they were going to develop so as to attract patients, grants, as well as the large pharmaceutical laboratories, so that they could conduct large-scale trials. But a few years later, Dr. Potti was implicated both from inside the science world by biostatisticians (Baggerly & Coombes 2009) and from the outside, through professional letters showing the many "enhancements" that had appeared on his resumé (Goldberg 2010), and then by his patients' families attracted by the potentially revolutionary character of his practices, who had sued for having been deceived.
Conclusion
Emphasizing how long these problems have been around, we had a double objective: first,
showing the emblematic value of certain cases, truly striking episodes that have produced
preventive measures so that these practices would not continue; second, taking stock of the
increase in the number of affairs revealed that have led to the retraction of articles as a clue
to a "surveillance bias." Just as certain fraudulent practices have become simpler to carry
out, the detection and dissemination of behaviors considered problematic has been largely
facilitated. For example, journals such as
Anaesthesia routinely use plagiarism detection
software, but it is also possible to construct tables that juxtapose text from several articles,
showing how close they are, putting together a series of an author's variable conflicts of
interest, or anonymously denounce image falsification by circulating a video clip4.
The recurrent stakes in all of these problematic situations revolves around the scientific community's ability to self-regulate. Nearly all of the institutional measures describe herein directly involve academic authors. Yet for the last 15 years, we have seen the journals themselves be targeted, notably in recurrent debates aiming to assess the independence of journal editors (Davis & Müllner 2002) and to reform peer review (Weicher 2008). What should be thought of the responsibility of
A&A which for years published Dr. Fujii's articles after the first meta-analyses? How should the process leading the
Journal of Clinical Microbiology to publish a plagiarized article published a few years early in its own columns be qualified5? Like researchers, journals are also subjected to conflicts of interest (Friedman
3 These guidelines were revised in 2000, and the member journals of the ICMJE took a position on conflicts of interest the following year in a common editorial titled "Sponsorship, Authorship, and Accountability" praising transparency and academic independence. A conflict of interest disclosure form common to all the ICMJE journals was established in 2010. 4 http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=FXaOqwanWnU 5 http://retractionwatch.wordpress.com/2011/09/01/should-journals-apologize-to-victims-of-plagiarism-more-on-journal-of-clinical-microbiology-case/
& Richter 2005; Lundh et al. 2010) and to the imperatives of success, partly founded on their impact factor, that incite them to introduce references motivated solely by journal citation (Smith 1997), a practice recently qualified as "coercive citations" (Wilhite & Fong 2012).
Symmetrically, the case of Dr. Fujii reminds us that journals have a tremendous collective organizational power, widely implemented in the authorship and conflict of interest reforms. In addressing their letter to research institutions, journals have placed them before their own responsibility, thus attempting to reverse the burden of proof. However, the distribution of the responsibility between the actors of academia is also played out on another level: the responsibility with regard to patients, the eventual victims of deviant behaviors (Steen 2011b). Indeed, if research having consequences in terms of treatments, prevention modalities, or, more generally, public health is at the heart of conflicts of interest, opening it to nonacademic actors allows new criticisms to be expressed and taken into consideration through judicial and political action on the part of users and citizens.
Acknowledgements
We thank Anne Bertrand (EHESS) for her careful reading of the manuscript and her
suggestions on an earlier version. Most of the recent affairs studied in this article stem
directly or indirectly from their revelation in the blog
Retraction Watch, maintained by Adam
Marcus and Ivan Oransky. We thank them for their meticulous and nearly daily work
assembling this information.
References
Abraham J. 1994. Bias in Science and Medical Knowledge: The Opren Controversy.
Sociology. 28:
717-736.
Baggerly K.A., Coombes K.R. 2009. Deriving chemosensitivity from cell lines: Forensic bioinformatics and reproducible research in high-throughput biology.
The Annals of Applied Statistics.3:1309-1334.
Bekelman J.E. 2003. Scope and Impact of Financial Conflicts of Interest in Biomedical Research: A Systematic Review.
Journal of the American Medical Association. 289: 454-465.
Biagioli M. 1998. The instability of authorship: credit and responsibility in contemporary biomedicine.
The FASEB journal. 12: 3-16.
Broad W.J. 1981. The publishing game: getting more for less.
Science. 211: 1137.
Broad W.J., Wade N. 1982.
Betrayers of the Truth; Fraud and Deceit in the Halls of Science. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Carlisle J.B. 2012. The analysis of 169 randomised controlled trials to test data integrity.
Anaesthesia. 67:521-537.
Cisterna R., Ezpeleta G., Telleria O., Regueiro B., Esperalba J. 2011. Nationwide sentinel surveillance of bloodstream Candida infections in 40 tertiary care hospitals in Spain.
Journal of Clinical Microbiology. 49: 1193.
Collectif. 2012. Joint Editors-in-Chief Request for Determination 1 Regarding Papers Published by Dr. Yoshitaka Fujii. http://www.aaeditor.org/Fujii_Joint_EIC_Stmt.pdf.
Corrigan O. 2003. Empty ethics: the problem with informed consent.
Sociology of Health & Illness.25: 768-792.
Coughlin S. 1997. Invited Commentary: On the Role of Ethics Committees in Epidemiology Professional Societies.
American Journal of Epidemiology. 146: 209-213.
Davis R.M., Müllner M. 2002. Editorial independence at medical journals owned by professional associations: a survey of editors.
Science and Engineering Ethics. 8: 513-528.
DeFrancesco C. 2012. Scientific Journals Notified Fol owing Research Misconduct Investigation. UConn Today. http://today.uconn.edu/blog/2012/01/scientific-journals-notified-following-research-misconduct-investigation/.
Etzkowitz H. 1996. Conflicts of interest and commitment in academic science in the United States.
Minerva. 34: 259-77.
Fanelli D. 2009. How many scientists fabricate and falsify research? A systematic review and meta-analysis of survey data.
PloS One. 4: e5738.
Fanelli D. 2010. Do pressures to publish increase scientists' bias? An empirical support from US States Data.
PloS One. 5: e10271.
Fang F.C., Casadevall A. 2011. Retracted science and the retraction index.
Infection and Immunity.79: 3855-3859.
Flanagin A., Carey L.A., Fontanarosa P.B., Phillips S.G., Pace B.P., Lundberg G.D., et al. 1998. Prevalence of articles with honorary authors and ghost authors in peer-reviewed medical journals.
Journal of the American Medical Association. 280: 222-224.
Freund Y., Chenevier-Gobeaux C., Claessens Y.E., Leumani F., Doumenc B., Bonnet P., et al. 2012. Retraction of "Concomitant measurement of copeptin and high-sensitivity troponin for fast and reliable rule out of acute myocardial infarction".
Incentive Care Medicine. 38: 733-744.
Friedman L.S., Richter E.D. 2004. Relationship between conflicts of interest and research results.
Journal of General Internal Medicine. 19: 51-56.
Friedman L., Richter E.D. 2005. Conflicts of interest and scientific integrity.
International Journal of Occupational and Environmental Health. 11: 205-206.
Fugh-Berman A., McDonald C.P., Bell A.M., Bethards E.C., Scialli A.R. 2011. Promotional tone in reviews of menopausal hormone therapy after the Women's Health Initiative: an analysis of published articles.
PLoS Medicine. 8: e1000425.
Furman J.L., Jensen K., Murray F. 2012. Governing knowledge in the scientific community: Exploring the role of retractions in biomedicine.
Research Policy. 41: 276-90.
Gingras Y., Gosselin P-M. 2008. The emergence and evolution of the expression "conflict of interests" in Science: a historical overview, 1880-2006.
Science and Engineering Ethics. 14: 337-343.
Goldberg P. 2010. Prominent Duke scientist claimed prizes he didn't win, including Rhodes scholarchip.
The Cancer Letter. 36(27): 1-7.
Gottweis H., Kim B. 2009. Explaining Hwang-Gate: South Korean Identity Politics between Bionationalism and Globalization.
Science, Technology & Human Values. 35: 501-24.
Hamilton D.P. 1990. Publishing by – and for ? – the numbers.
Science. 250: 1331-1332.
Hansen M. 2012. Statement From Michael Hansen, CEO Of Elsevier's Health Sciences Division, Regarding Australia Based Sponsored Journal Practices Between 2000 And 2005. Elsevier. http://www.elsevier.com/wps/find/authored_newsitem.cws_home/companynews05_01203.
Huth E.J. 1986. Irresponsible authorship and wasteful publication.
Annals of Internal Medicine.104: 257-259.
Ioannidis J.P. 2005. Why most published research findings are false.
PLoS Medicine. 2: e124.
Kanaan Z., Galandiuk S., Abby M., Shannon K.V., Dajani D., Hicks N., et al. 2011. The value of lesser-impact-factor surgical journals as a source of negative and inconclusive outcomes reporting.
Annals of Surgery. 253: 619-623.
Kranke P., Apfel C.C., Eberhart L., Georgieff M., Roewer N. 2001. The influence of a dominating centre on a quantitative systematic review of granisetron for preventing postoperative nausea and vomiting.
Acta Anaesthesiologica Scandinavica. 5: 659-70.
Kranke P., Apfel C.C., Roewer N. 2012. Response.
Anesthesia & Analgesia. 90: 1004-1007.
Krimsky S., Rothenberg L.S. 2001. Conflict of interest policies in science and medical journals: editorial practices and author disclosures.
Science and Engineering Ethics. 7: 205-218.
Lafolette M.C. 1992.
Stealing into Print: Fraud, Plagarism, and Misconduct in Science. Berkeley and Los-Angeles: University of California Press.
Lee K., Bacchetti P., Sim I. 2008. Publication of Clinical Trials Supporting Successful New Drug Applications: A Literature Analysis.
PLoS Medicine. 5: e191.
Lexchin J., Bero L., Djulbegovic B. 2003. Pharmaceutical industry sponsorship and research outcome and quality: systematic review.
British Medical Journal. 326: 1167-1170.
Lundh A., Barbateskovic M., Hróbjartsson A., Gøtzsche P.C. 2010. Conflicts of interest at medical journals: the influence of industry-supported randomised trials on journal impact factors and revenue - cohort study.
PLoS Medicine. 7: e1000354.
Lynch M., Woolgar S. (eds). 1990.
Representation in scientific practice. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.
Maddox J. 1988. Why the pressure to publish?
Nature. 333: 493.
Marcus A., Oransky I. 2011. The paper is not sacred.
Nature. 480: 449-450.
Marks H. 1999.
La Médecine des preuves. Histoire et anthropologie des essais cliniques (1900-1990). Paris: Synthélabo, Les Empecheurs de penser en rond.
Melander H., Ahlqvist-Rastad J., Meijer G., Beermann B. 2003. Evidence b(i)ased medicine – selective reporting from studies sponsored by pharmaceutical industry: review of studies in new drug applications.
British Medical Journal. 326: 1171-1173.
Merton R.K. 1942. Science and technology in a democratic order.
Journal of Legal and Political Sociology. 1: 115-126.
Miller D.R. 2012. Expression of concern.
Canadian Journal of Anesthesia. 1-8.
Mirowski P. 2005. The Contract Research Organization and the Commercialization of Scientific Research.
Social Studies of Science. 35: 503-548.
Moore R.A, Derry S., McQuay H.J. 2010. Fraud or flawed: adverse impact of fabricated or poor quality research.
Anaesthesia. 65: 327-30.
Pearce N. 2008. Corporate influences on epidemiology.
International Journal of Epidemiology. 7: 46-53.
Pontille D. 2001. L'auteur scientifique en question: pratiques en psychologie et en sciences biomédicales.
Social Science Information. 40: 433-453.
Pontille D. 2004.
La signature scientifique. Une sociologie pragmatique de l'attribution. Paris: CNRS Editions.
Proctor R., Schiebinger L. 2008. Agnotology:
The Making and Unmaking of Ignorance: Stanford University Press.
Rennie D., Flanagin A. 1994. Authorship! Authorship! Guests, ghosts, grafters, and the two-sided coin.
Journal of the American Medical Association. 271: 469-471.
Rosner D. 2005. Standing Up to the Lead Industry : An Interview with Herbert Needleman.
Public Health Reports. 120: 330-337.
Schafer A. 2004. Biomedical conflicts of interest: a defence of the sequestration thesis – learning from the cases of Nancy Olivieri and David Healy.
Journal of Medical Ethics. 30: 8-24.
Shafer S.L. 2012. Statement of concern.
Anesthesia & Analgesia. 1-6. http://www.aaeditor.org/FujiiStatementOfConcern.pdf
Shapin S., Schaffer S. 1985.
Leviathan and the air-pump. Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life. Princeton, New-Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Simes R.J. 1986. Publication bias: the case for an international registry of clinical trials.
Journal of Clinical Oncology. 4: 1529-1541.
Sismondo S. 2007. Ghost management: how much of the medical literature is shaped behind the scenes by the pharmaceutical industry?
PLoS Medicine. 4: e286.
Smith R. 1997. Journal accused of manipulating impact factor.
British Medical Journal. 314: 1-2.
Smith R. 2005. Medical journals are an extension of the marketing arm of pharmaceutical companies.
PLoS Medicine. 2: e138.
Steen R.G. 2011a. Retractions in the scientific literature: do authors deliberately commit research fraud?
Journal of Medical Ethics. 37: 113-117.
Steen R.G. 2011b. Retractions in the medical literature: how many patients are put at risk by flawed research?
Journal of Medical Ethics. 37: 688-692.
Stern J.M, Simes R.J. 1997. Publication bias: evidence of delayed publication in a cohort study of clinical research projects.
British Medical Journal. 315: 640-645.
Stewart W., Feder N. 1987. The integrity of the scientific literature.
Nature. 325: 207-214.
Susser M., Yankauer A. 1993. Prior, Duplicate, Repetitive, Fragmented, and Redundant Publication and Editonial Decisions.
American Journal of Public Health. 83: 792-793.
Torny D. 2003. Une mémoire pour le futur. La traçabilité comme allocateur de responsabilité. In: Pedrot P, editor.
Traçabilité et responsabilité. Paris: Economica. 72-87.
Tramèr M.R, Reynolds D.J.M., Moore R.A., McQuay H.J. 1997. Impact of covert duplicate publication on meta-analysis: a case study.
British Medical Journal. 315: 635-640.
Turner E.H., Knoepflmacher D., Shapley L. 2012. Publication Bias in Antipsychotic Trials: An Analysis of Efficacy Comparing the Published Literature to the US Food and Drug Administration Database.
PLoS Medicine. 9: e1001189.
Turner E.H., Matthews A.M., Linardatos E., Tell R., Rosenthal R. 2008. Selective publication of antidepressant trials and its influence on apparent efficacy.
New England Journal of Medicine.358: 252-260.
Van Noorden R. 2011. The trouble with retractions.
Nature. 478: 26-28.
Wager E. 2012. Who is responsible for investigating suspected research misconduct?
Anaesthesia.;67: 462-466.
Weed D.L., McKeown R.E. 1998. Epidemiology and virtue ethics.
International Journal of Epidemiology.27: 343-349.
Weicher M. 2008. Peer review and secrecy in the "Information Age".
Proceedings of the American Society for Information Science and Technology. 45(1): 1-12.
Wilhite A.W., Fong E.A. 2012. Coercive Citation in Academic Publishing.
Science. 335: 542-543.
Yentis S.M. 2010. Another kind of ethics: from corrections to retractions.
Anaesthesia. 65: 1163-1166.
Source: http://www.i-3.fr/wp-content/uploads/2013/01/I3WP_13-MS-03.pdf
Recommendations for improved sustainable priority Neglected Species NUS in Vietnam Nguyen Lam, Nguyen The Phuong and Pham Thi Dung Funded by the European Commission's sixth framework programme: "Integrating and Strengthening the European Research Area, Specific Measures in Support of International Cooperation (INCO)". fp6-2002-inco-dev/ssa-1 – 026293
For permission to use or duplicate this manuscript, please contact Vanessa Jackson P.O. Box 10796,Atlanta, GA 30310 The content of this publication does not necessarily reflect the views or policies of the Center for Mental Health Services (CMHS), Substance Abuse Mental Health Services Administration (SAMHSA), or the Department of Health and Human Services (HHS).